Uncertainty in medicine: Clich or oblivion
Bernard W K Lau 劉偉楷
Human beings are, to some degree or other, afraid of uncertainty; and if possible
we always work towards seeking certainty. There seems in our culture to be an expectation
that doctors always have the answers and they are presumed to be experts in knowing,
but unfortunately uncertainty is a way of life for doctors. In reality, there is
at least a grain of truth that medical knowledge is often engulfed and infiltrated
by a certain degree of uncertainty,1 which is defined as the inability
to determine the meaning of events, in a situation where the decision-maker is unable
to predict outcomes accurately.2 That is, given current knowledge, more
than one event is often possible. That is why a clinical condition may have several,
if not many, differential diagnoses and in the same vein a patient's problem may
indeed have more than one determinant cause. In medicine, one wins a diagnostic
gamble by believing and acting on a correct diagnosis or by rejecting an incorrect
diagnosis. Or one loses by believing and acting on an incorrect diagnosis or by
rejecting a correct diagnosis. For a doctor trained in the Mechanistic Paradigm's
model of causality, he will prefer to work from the heuristic principle:
"Find the cause, then treat". Without a known cause there seems to be no clear basis
for treatment, and the doctor is often uneasy with whatever treatment he undertakes.3
For all concerned in health care, the passion for certainty will keep costs high.
It leads the doctor to use whatever technology is available to obtain a less equivocal
diagnosis, and it also leads patients to demand such diagnostic overkill. Even when
doctors themselves do not see a need to perform all the prescribed procedures, they
may do so anyway to protect themselves against malpractice suits in which the courts
apply medicine's own standards of certainty. By those standards a doctor must do
something necessary to be certain as is possible before acting.3
In most cases uncertainty is easily tolerated because the consequences of getting
it wrong are relatively unimportant (for example, is the patient's sore throat due
to virus or bacterium?). Uncertainty is more stressful when misdiagnosis may have
dire consequences, and most doctors would go as far as possible to reduce uncertainty
when they believe the probability of serious illness is high.4
While patients might be interested to know the diagnosis, sometimes this means very
little to them and it is prognosis that is more important to them as individuals.5
Questions about prognosis frequently raised by patients and their families take
varying forms:
When will I get better? Will I be completely well? What are the chances of the disease
recurring? No doubt, one of the most difficult tasks in medicine is predicting how
long someone with a terminal illness may live. No accurate method is usually available,
largely because of the multiple variables that influence when a patient will die.6
When considering prognosis, the doctor must make a complete diagnosis relating the
pathology present to the individual concerned. Even when an accurate diagnosis can
be made, it can be notoriously difficult to predict the course of events in a given
instance of a disease. In general practice the diagnosis is often in doubt, at least
in the early or undifferentiated stages, and this further complicates the task.5,8
In so far as prognosis implies a forecast of the probable course and result of an
illness, particularly with regard to the prospect of recovery,7 such
a prediction always contains an element of irreducible uncertainty. Uncertainty
in prediction simply means that, given current knowledge, there are multiple possible
future states of nature. Moreover, any prediction involving people tends to be misleading,
precisely because the numbers needed to make accurate predictions are so huge. The
result is that predictions become meaningless - because they do not apply to any
individual person.9 This is where the beauty of evidence-based medicine
comes in.
Essentially evidence-based medicine is a process of having clinical practice based
on validated information.10 This approach suggests that a doctor should
use the best available evidence when making a decision to use a diagnostic test
or choose a treatment.11 However, it must be acknowledged that evidence-based
practice is no panacea.4 Even its proponents make no pretence that it
can provide all the answers. The main criticism against it is that it may foster
the rigidity of "cookbook medicine" based on the biased opinions of western scientific
medicine and statistics, at the expense of ignoring the art of medicine and individual
patient and physician and patient variation in experience and judgement.12
The contention is that there has always been a place in medicine for clinical judgement
that is based on personal experience and intuition and that takes into account intangible
factors such as physician's knowledge of a particular patient or family. Traditionally
this kind of skill has been thought of as "the art of medicine".3
By all means good medicine would allow probability estimates to be derived not only
from tables of figures, but also from the subjective judgement of the doctor, patient,
and family. It means that a doctor's knowledge of a particular patient's history
may be more useful than statistical tables in assessing the likelihood that the
patient has a particular disease or will respond to a particular treatment. And
it means that there may be times when the patient or the patient's family are better
judges of these probabilities than the doctor, especially a doctor who does not
have prior knowledge of the patient.3
There is a saying in medicine that every patient is unique and should therefore
deserve to be treated judiciously as a different individual from others. In any
event, what appropriate evidence-based medicine should be in any locality in the
world is again a matter of judgement.
It is possible that shared decision-making,13,14 a particular type of
doctor-patient interaction whereby the patient brings his/her individual preferences
and the doctor contributes the medical expertise, is a partial solution to the current
state of medical uncertainty.15 Moreover, shared decision-making has
been shown to lead to higher rates of satisfaction and better treatment results.
This might be an area worthy of more research.
Hence, is the problem one of uncertain diagnosis or uncertain management? At the
end of the day, it may well be the uncertain doctor, as ultimately it is the doctor,
who plays the key role in managing uncertainty.8 It would seem that as
long as medical uncertainty is part of reality in life, as veracious as the Heisenberg
Uncertainty Principle, we may have to put up with it, after all. It then begs the
question: is it good enough to be sure beyond reasonable doubt, not beyond all doubt?
Editors' Note
This editorial was written by Bernard shortly before his sudden and unexpected death
on June 13th.
Bernard was a regular contributor to the College journal. A thoughtful, kind and
considerate person who was never afraid to offer his opinion nor to challenge the
accepted paradigm.
We struggled with the decision to publish this piece, but in the end decided that
Bernards' own words should speak for him. He will be sadly missed.
References
- Katz J. The silent world of doctor and patient. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University
Press, 2002.
- Royer A. Life with chronic illness. Westport: Praeger, 1998.
- Bursztajn HJ. Medical choices, medical chances. New York: Routlege, 1990.
- Ridsdale L. Evidence-based practice in primary care. Edinburgh: Churchill Livingstone,
1998.
- Morrel D. The art of general practice. Oxford: Oxford Medical Publications, 1991.
- Rakel RE. Textbook of Family Medicine. Philadelphia, Saunders, 2002.
- Seale C, Pattison S, Davey B. Medical knowledge: Doubt and uncertainty. Buckingham:
OUP, 2001.
- Jones R, Britten N, Culpepper L, et al. Oxford Textbook of primary medical care.
Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004.
- Cole KC. The Universe and the teacup: The mathematics of truth and beauty. London:
Abacus, 1998.
- Murtagh J. General Practice. Sydney: McGraw-Hill, 2003.
- Ebell MH. Evidence-Based Diagnosis. New York: Springer, 2001.
- Gabbay M. The Evidence-Based Primary Care Handbook. London: RSMP, 1999.
- Frosch DL, Kaplan RM. Shared decision making in clinical medicine: Past research
and future directions. Am J Prev Med 1999;17: 285-294.
- Scheibler F, Janssen C, Pfaff H. Shared decision making: An overview of international
research literature. Sozial-und-Praventivmedizin 2003;48:11-23.
- Ghosh AK. Dealing with medical uncertainty: A physician's perspective. Minn Med
2004;87:48-51.
|