To die a dignified death
Stephen Chen 陳紹德
HK Pract 2007;29:217-219
On 17 August 1935, Charlotte Perkins Gilman, writer and an advocate of the right-to-die,
took an overdose of chloroform to pre-empt a perceived horrific ending from cancer.
Her suicide note is still a relevant plea nowadays for the right to die in dignity
when all pertinent treatment fails with the following message.
"When all usefulness is over, when one is assured of an unavoidable and imminent
death, it is the simplest of human rights to choose a quick and easy death in place
of a slow and horrible one."
Therein for some lies the crux of the advocacy of the right of patients with terminal
illnesses to choose to die in a dignified way. The importance of patients (and their
immediate relatives) being sufficiently informed about their incurable clinical
conditions and given the right to choose to bow out of this world, whether bedridden
or wheelchair-bound, yet comfortably and gracefully, is well-illustrated in an article
written by a British General Practitioner.1
Voluntary euthanasia has until recently been avoided by the local media and medical
profession as a topic for discussion due probably to its controversial nature and
the Oriental tendency to circumnavigate or sidestep confrontational issues. Nevertheless,
it is precisely because of the ethical, medicolegal and religious complexities,
as well as the human rights concern involved that we should endeavour to tackle
the issue head-on. It is only with open uninhibited and well-informed discussions
that the barriers of bigotry can be broken down, consensus of opinion reached and
empathic understanding attained.
World media interest in the topic has recently been rekindled by a widely reported
case2 in Italy, where a male patient (Piergiorgio Welby) paralyzed by
progressive muscular dystrophy failed to win a court battle for the right to die,
but succeeded in securing his doctor's (Mario Riccio's) consent to ending his miserable
existence by switching off the respirator - Welby's unwanted raison d'tre. The attending
physician gave the patient a sedative prior to switching off the respirator, on
which Welby's bedridden life totally depended. Having expressed "thank you" three
times to his wife, friends and doctor at the outset of his chosen finale, Welby
died peacefully and presumably comfortably 45 minutes later. A politician (well,
who else would indulge in such opportunism!) in Italy has accused Dr Riccio of homicide
and called for his arrest, but it is hitherto uncertain if the humanitarianism-motivated
doctor will be charged with any offence.
On the Eastern front, a 28 year old girl (Li Yan) in Liaoning Province3
in mainland China submitted a request for voluntary euthanasia to the Central Government
via a representative member of the Central People's Consultative Committee, whilst
simultaneously sending her death wish to the Central Television Studio for broadcasting.
Li is also a sufferer of progressive muscular dystrophy and since one year old,
has relentlessly deteriorated to the current status of being able to only slightly
move her head and a few fingers. She is totally reliant on her mother for feeding,
urination, defaecation and cleansing. Even when sleeping in bed, she is dependent
on others to turn her more than ten times nightly so as to avoid bedsores.
"I love life, but I do not wish to live."
(我愛生命,但我不願活。)
"A human being not only has the right to live, but also the freedom to die."
(人有生的權利,也有死的自由。)
These two quotes have been translated verbatim from Li's Chinese text and this author
takes responsibility for any inaccuracy contained therein. She wants to end her
already miserable existence before her parents die for obvious reasons expounded
above; and also when she can still sit in a chair and has the capacity for speech,
in short, when she still possesses a certain degree of personal dignity. Li vowed
she would donate all her functional organs to medical research if granted her death
wish. When asked what she would do if her plea for voluntary euthanasia was rejected,
Li indicated that the only alternative is for her to starve herself to death (surely
a slow painful one and seemingly inhumane to any bystanders) because she has lost
all ability to hold any weapon to kill herself more instantly.
The two cases in opposite corners of the world highlight the dilemma doctors face
when managing patients with terminal illnesses. Whilst it is a patient's basic human
right to decline life-sustaining treatment, is it ethically correct for doctors
to partake of voluntary euthanasia or assisted suicide?
Medicolegally, a prerequisite for any treatment is a patient's informed consent,
unless in dire life-saving situations. If a patient is mentally incapable of giving
such informed consent, then the closest next-of-kin should assume the responsibility.
Doctors cannot impose unwanted treatment, however justifiable or desirable, on reluctant
patients; otherwise the criminal charge of assault or grievous bodily harm may be
filed. Doctors may disagree with patients' decision not to undergo certain treatment,
but professionally they should respect the patients' right to such tenet. Most countries
recognize a patient's legal right to refuse medical treatment, and in a few, namely,
the Netherlands, Switzerland, Belgium and the American state of Oregon, doctors
are even allowed to assist patients with medicolegally justifiable reasons to achieve
voluntary euthanasia by means other than stopping on-going treatment. In other words,
doctors in these minority countries are allowed to partake of assisted suicide,
thus enabling patients with terminal illnesses to die in whatever personal dignity
they still retain, i.e. "a quick and easy death in place of a slow and horrible
one".
Let us consider Welby and Li in juxtaposition as the two cases bear some resemblance
to each other. If Dr Riccio had not switched off the respirator because of his patient's
refusal to undergo the said treatment any further, Welby would probably have had
to starve himself to death, thus a "slow and horrible one" and surely a much more
inhumane way of ending one's life. Li also threatens to starve herself to death
if her request for voluntary euthanasia is not officially granted. However, in Li's
case, she is not yet reliant on a life-sustaining respirator which can be simply
withdrawn. To enable Li achieve her goal, the participating doctor would be involved
in an act of assisted suicide, which is still illegal and medico-ethically frowned
on in most countries.
In 1980 Pope John Paul II approved the Declaration on Euthanasia which states that
refusal of burdensome medical treatment "is not the equivalent of suicide".4
The Catholic Church has for a long time subscribed to the view that use of "extraordinary"
or "disproportionate" ways to prolong life is not obligatory. Furthermore, the refusal
of such burdensome treatment "should be considered an acceptance of the human condition,
or a wish to avoid the application of a medical procedure disproportionate to the
results that can be expected, or a desire not to impose excessive expense on the
family or the community".4 Nevertheless, the Catholic Church is still
opposed to voluntary euthanasia and assisted suicide per se.
The Netherlands was the first country to legalize voluntary euthanasia and has since
witnessed a change in government; but there has been no relevant statutory repeal
despite allegations from critics that such legalization has engendered a breakdown
of trust in the medical profession and other adverse sequelae. According to Peter
Singer, Professor of bioethics at Princeton University, "the Dutch know that legalizing
voluntary euthanasia has improved, rather than harmed, medical care, and they want
the possibility of assistance in dying".2 As Benjamin Franklin (1706
- 1790) once said, "in this world, nothing is certain but death and taxes", perhaps
we should all spare some time to ponder over Professor Singer's soul-searching question
on the possibility of assistance in dying -
Professional competence is multi-dimensional; it is not possible to have one single
test that can validly and reliably measure all the required indicators. Multiple
methods have to be used to determine whether a candidate has achieved the required
level of competence. An adequate number of questions and examiners should be used
to improve the reliability. Clearly defined assessment criteria are essential to
ensure fairness. Standards should be set at an absolute level to assure the quality
of the profession.
Assessment is a complex form of measurement. All measurements reflect not only the
true result (the candidate's competence) but also variations that are related to
the assessment content and context, examiners and other unknown factors. Research
has shown that candidate factors explain no more than 50% of the variance in the
results.7 No assessment is perfect; we can only try to make it as good
as possible through a rational choice of methods and questions, fair setting of
criteria and standards, and adequate examiner training.
"Isn't that a choice that everyone should have?"2
Stephen Chen, MSc Occ Med (Lond), Dip Sports Med (Lond), DTM&H (Lond)
Honorary Clinical Assistant Professor in Family Medicine,
Department of Medicine, Family Medicine Unit, The University of Hong Kong.
Correspondence to : Dr Stephen Chen, c/o HKCFP, 7th Floor, HKAM Jockey Club
Building, 99 Wong Chuk Hang Road, Hong Kong.
References
- Newton P. A good death - but no thanks to the NHS. Personal View. BMJ 2007; 334:536.
- Singer P. Voluntary euthanasia. The right to choose help in dying. South China Morning
Post, 20 January 2007:A15.
- 都市. 重病女生望人大助安樂死. Metro Daily News, 14 March 2007:8.
- Quoted by Singer P, South China Morning Post, 20 January 2007:A15.
|